“We are most
revealed in what we do not scrutinize” claims Gould
(qtd. in Mishra 141). I think this quote could be used to talk about all three
texts by Mishra (“The Role of Abstraction in Scientific Illustration: Implications
for Pedagogy”), Lakoff and Johnson (Metaphors
We Live By—I’m guessing is the book),
and Gross (“Rhetorical Analysis”). In other words, we are most revealed by
what we assume.
Assumptions mask
values—and beyond that, belief systems. Lakoff and Johnson describe metaphorical
“concepts we live by,” which are basically “assumptions” we make at a
linguistic level. For example, they point out our metaphorical concept that “argument
is war” (4-6). Though they explain how
we contrive argument as war, they don’t explain why we have arrived at this subtle conceptual metaphor (in
contrast, note their explanation for the “time is money” metaphor on pages
8-9). Perhaps we “assume” that argument is war because we (at least Americans)
value the idea of “winning” and superiority brought about by hard work and
individualistic effort. Of course, even the values underlying this metaphorical
concept of “argument is war” are metaphorical in nature, which leads us to
question whether our values shape metaphor or metaphor shapes our values (a
classic “chicken vs. egg” debate)…
Nonetheless, we
might still pursue the idea that values underlie assumptions. Gross points out
the common faulty assumption that science is emotionless and passionless: “the
general freedom of scientific prose from emotional appeal must be understood
not as neutrality but as a deliberate abstinence: the assertion of a value” (574).
That value is “objectivity,” an emphasis on reason versus “unreasonable”
emotion (an assumption in itself). Mishra’s discussion about a diagram of a
heart compared to an actual heart (146-147) on one hand supports the assertion
that diagrams are inherently symbolic for the express purpose of better
understanding the reality; on the other hand, the “neat arrangements” of the
diagrammed heart reveals our value for orderliness (we can control order, not
chaos; ultimately, underneath the value of orderliness is the value of power).
We function by
making assumptions—otherwise, we’d never be able to do anything. Just think
about all the assumptions we make even waking up in the morning: 1) There’s a
reality outside of me, and therefore, the alarm I’m hearing is an actual
stimulus and not part of my imagination 2) the alarm is ringing, so it must be
6 am 3) I have to wake up because it’s a school day 4) I can’t miss classes
because my grades will worsen…etc. etc. That’s a silly example (with a ton of
assumptions built into each “assumption” itself), but I hope that it gets my
point across: essentially, we are assumption-making beings. Assumptions, after
all, aren’t always bad things; they are what make language and communication
feasible.
However,
assumptions also limit the scope of what we can “see”: “The very systematicity
that allows us to comprehend one aspect of a concept in terms of another…will
necessarily hide other aspects of the concept” (Lakoff and Johnson 10).
Following the same lines, Root-Bernstein says, “Pictures, tables, graphs can be
dangerous things. Revealing one point, they hide assumptions, eliminate
possibilities, prevent comparisons—silently, unobviously. Thus, a pattern makes
sense of data but also limits what sense it can make up” (qtd. in Mishra 154). Throughout
many of these blog posts, we’ve examined the uncertain nature of language,
knowledge, and truth functioning in science; some of us have even come to the
conclusion that “truth” and “knowledge” are both unstable constructs invented
by humans. According to certain kinds of theoretical frameworks, these
conclusions appear to make sense. However, the frameworks themselves are a sort
of assumption which allows us to see
certain things while at the same time obscuring others.
In the
particular framework we’ve been using, we’ve discounted the existence of
absolute, certain truth or knowledge because we assume that we can’t be given
them from an outside source; in other words, we write off the possession of absolute
truth or knowledge because we disbelieve in supernatural revelation. Underlying
this assumption is probably a multitude of different values: the value of
independence, freedom from judgment, and control over one’s life, to list a
few. And yet, tied to the assumption that a higher power doesn’t exist are
other assumptions as well: if a good, all-powerful God were real, pain wouldn’t
exist in the world; nothing can exist without a cause; physical bodies couldn’t
reside in “heaven”—assumptions and questions Quinn brings up in her article, “Sign
Here If You Exist.”
I think it’s
interesting that in his syllabus, Doug decided to label the two readings for
Thursday as “Choosing truths.” The nuance of the word “choosing” makes me
regard it as something done on an arbitrary whim, just as I would happen to “choose”
chocolate ice cream over vanilla ice cream. But perhaps this impression is
exactly the intent of the phrase. Earlier in the semester, I wrote a blog post
about the “Faith of Science,” and both Liam and Doug (in a follow-up email)
made excellent counterpoints about the nature of evidence and how we qualify good evidence. Doug wrote, “From the
very earliest ages, we find ourselves able to have faith in something because
we already have faith in something else.” Basically, we
already have faith in the very evidences we use as the basis for faith in
something else. It all goes back to assumptions. What if someone asserts, “Reasoning
is futile nonsense”? Most of us would disagree with this statement, but we can’t
prove it because the only way to
argue with this statement would be to reason
about it—which is a circular argument. We “know” that reasoning isn’t “futile
nonsense” because we take it on faith (J. Budziszewski).
If most of our
knowledge—and reason itself—is taken on faith (which could be thought of as
assumptions), then how do we “choose”?
“But which side will you choose? Reason cannot
decide for us one war or the other; we are separated by an infinite gulf. A
game is on, at the other side of this infinite distance, where either heads or
tails may turn up. Which will you wager on?” ~Blaise Pascal
No comments:
Post a Comment